When is a person not a person?
II
«Someone has a desire of a second-order either when he wants
simply to have a certain desire or when he wants a certain desire to be his
will. In situations of the latter kind, I shall call his second-desires “ second-order
volitions” or “ volitions of the second-order”. Now it is having second-order
volitions, and not having second-order volitions, and not having second-order
desires generally, that I regard as essential to being a person. It is
logically possible, however unlikely, that there should be an agent with
second-order desires but with no volitions of the second-order. Such a creature,
in my view, would not be a person. I shall use the term “wanton” to refer to
agents who have first-order desires but who are not persons because, whether or
not they have desires of the second-order, they have no second-order volitions.[i]
You can get this fridge magnet on e-Bay? But why? |
«The essential characteristic of a wanton is that he does not
care about his will. His desires move him to do certain things, without its
being true of him either that he wants to be moved by those desires or that he
prefers to be moved by other desires. The class of wantons includes all
non-human animals and all very young children. Perhaps it also includes some
adult human beings as well. In any case, adult humans may be more or less
wanton; they may act wantonly, in response to first-order desires concerning
which they have no volitions of the second-order, more or less frequently.
«The fact that a wanton has no second-order volitions does
not mean that each of his first-order desires is translated heedlessly ad at
once into action. He may have no opportunity to act in accordance with some of
his desires. Moreover, the translation of his desires into action may be
delayed or precluded either by conflicting desires of the first order or by the
intervention of deliberation. For a wanton may possess and employ rational
faculties of a high order. Nothing in the concept of a wanton implies that he
cannot reason or that he cannot deliberate concerning what he wants to do. What
distinguishes the rational wanton from other rational agents is that he is not
concerned with the desirability of his desires themselves. He ignores the
question of what his will is to be. Not only does he pursue whatever course of
action he is most strongly inclined to pursue, but he does not care which of his
inclinations is the strongest.
«Thus a rational creature, who reflects upon the suitability
of his desires of one course of action or another, may nonetheless be a wanton.
In maintaining that the essence of being a person lies not in reason but in
will, I am far from suggesting that a creature without reason may be person.
For it is only in virtue of his rational capacities that a person is capable of
becoming critically aware of his own will and of forming volitions of the
second order. The structure of a person’s will presupposes, accordingly, that
he is a rational being.
«The distinction between a person and a wanton may be illustrated
by the difference between two narcotics addicts. Let us suppose that the
physiological condition accounting for the addiction is the same in both men,
and that both succumb inevitably to their periodic desires for the drug to
which they are addicted. One of the addicts hates his addiction and always
struggles desperately, although to no avail, against its thrust. He tries
everything that he thinks might enable him to overcome his desires for the
drug. But these desires are too powerful for him to withstand, and invariably,
in the end, they conquer him. He is an unwilling addict, helplessly violated by
his own desires.
A wanton doesn't care about the outcome of inner struggles |
«The unwilling addict has conflicting first-order desires: he
wants to take the drug, and he also wants to refrain from taking it. In
addition to these first-order desires, however, he has a volition of the second
order. He is not a neutral with regard to the conflict between his desire to
take the drug and his desire to refrain from taking it. It is the latter
desire, and not the former, that he wants to constitute his will; it is the
latter desire rather than the former, that he wants to effective ad to provide
the purpose that he will seek to realize in what he actually does.
«The other addict is a wanton. His actions reflect the
economy of his first order desires, without hs being concerned whether the desires
that move him to act are desires by which he wants to be moved or act. If he
encounters problems in obtaining the drug or in administering it to himself,
his responses to his urges to take it may involve deliberation. But it never
occurs to him to consider whether he wants the relations among his desires to
result in his having the will he has. The wanton addict may be an animal, and
thus incapable of being concerned about his will. In any event, he is, in
respect of his wanton lack of concern, no different from an animal.
«The second of these addicts may suffer a first-order
conflict similar to the first-order conflict suffered by the first. Whether he
is human or not, the wanton may (perhaps due to conditioning) both want to take
the drug and want to refrain from taking it. Unlike the unwilling addict,
however, he does not prefer that one of his conflicting desires should be
paramount over the other; he does not prefer that one first-order desire rather
than the other should constitute his will. It would be misleading to say that
he is neutral as to the conflict between his desires, since this would suggest
that he regards them as equally acceptable. Since he has no identity apart from
his first-order desires, it is true neither that he prefers one to the other
nor that he prefers not to take sides.
I«t makes a difference to the unwilling addict, who is a person,
which of his conflicting desires wins out. Both desires are his, to be sure;
and whether he finally takes the drug or finally succeeds in refraining from
taking it, he acts to satisfy what is in a literal sense his own desire. In
either case he does something he himself wants to do, and he does it not
because of some external influence whose aim happens to coincide with his own
but because of his desire to do it. The unwilling addict identifies himself,
however, through the formation of a second-order volition, with one rather than
the other of his conflicting first-order desires. He makes one of them more truly
his own and, in so doing, he withdraws himself from the other. It is in virtue
of this identification and withdrawal, accomplished through the formation of a
second-order volition, that the unwilling addict may meaningfully make the
analytically puzzling statements that the force moving him to take the drug is
a force other than his own, and that it is not of his own free will but rather
against his will that this force moves him to take it.
«The wanton addict cannot or does not care which of his
conflicting first-order desires wins out. His lack of concern is not due to his
inability to find a convincing basis for preference. It is due either to his
lack of the capacity for reflection or to his mindless indifference to the
enterprise of evaluating his own desires and motives.[ii]
There is only one issue in the struggle to which his first-order conflict may
lead: whether the one or the other of his conflicting desires is the stronger.
Since he is moved by both desires, he will not be altogether satisfied by what
he does no matter which of them is effective. But it makes no difference to him whether his craving or his
aversion gets the upper hand. He has no
stake in the conflict between them, and so, unlike the unwilling addict, he can
neither win nor lose the struggle in which he is engaged. When a person acts, the desire by which he is
moved is either the will he wants or a will he wants to be without. When a
wanton acts, it is neither.»
[i]Creatures
with second-order desires but no second-order volitions differ significantly
from brute animals, and, for some purposes, it would be desirable to regard
them as persons. My usage, which withholds the designation “person” from them,
is thus somewhat arbitrary. I adopt it largely because it facilitates the
formulation of some of the points I wish to make. Hereafter, whenever I
consider statements of the form “A wants to want X,” I shall have in mind statements
identifying second-order volitions and not statements identifying second-order
desires that are not second-order volitions.
[ii]
In speaking of the evaluation of his own desires and motives as being
characteristic of a person, I do not mean to suggest that a person’s
second-order volitions necessarily manifest a moral stance on his part toward his first-order desires. It may not
be from the point of view of morality that the person evaluates his first-order
desires. Moreover a person may be capricious and irresponsible in forming his
second-order volitions and give no serious consideration to what is at stake.
Second-order volitions express evaluations only in the sense that they are
preferences. There is no essential restriction on the kind of basis, if any,
upon which they are formed.
No comments:
Post a Comment