Frankfurt’s Addicts
Frankfurt’s picture of what it is to be a person is a picture
of tensions and instability. This unsteadiness that lies at the heart of human
nature is traced to having two different kinds of desires where one checks or
qualifies in some way the other.
Frankfurt puts it like this: Besides wanting and choosing and being moved to do this or that, we may
also want to have (or not to have) certain desires or motives. They are capable
of wanting to be different, in their preferences and purposes, from what they
are. Many animals appear to have the capacity for what I shall call “first
order desires” or “desires of the first order”, which are simply desires to do
or not to do one thing or another. No animal other than man, however, appears
to have the capacity for reflective self-evaluation that is manifested in the
formation of second-order desires.
Like those molten mashes of rock that cooling at different
rates and pressures produce very different compounds and crystals, so people –
we might guess – turn out to have several differing but relatively stable
states. Something of this sort is illustrated by Frankfurt’s broad-brush
pictures of three different kinds of addicts.
Frankfurt’s analysis turns upon the concept of our ‘effective
will’. To identify an agent’s will is to identify the desire or
desires that would push him towards or all the way to action. Our second-order
desires, if they are really desires of the kind we take them to be – what Frankfurt
calls ‘volitions’ - , will act upon and in some sense modify our first-order
desires. This creates the possibility
for three types of addict in his illustrative bestiary:
A simulation of Brownian motion |
1 (1) The ‘wanton’: The wanton’s first-order desires for
drugs or money to obtain drugs and the like rule the roost in his life. He may
have second-order desires of many seemingly advanced and desirable kinds. He
might want to be a philosopher – a common desire among drug-addicts – or to be
seen as an upstanding CEO in the world of banking, but unless these desires are
volitions that he wants to make part of his will he is in effect simply driven
through life by his first-order desires. These may push him in many different
directions so that his life is like one of those particles of pollen that are
knocked this way or that across the surface of water by the random action of
fast-moving atoms or molecules. Frankfurt characterizes this extreme instance
like this: I shall use the term ‘wanton’ to refer to agents who have first-order
desires but who are not persons because, whether or not they have desires of
the second-order, they have no second-order volitions. Frankfurt’s wanton
is a logical extreme, though one might call to mind images of clapped out rock
stars who have had far too much of what they wanted. The essential
characteristic of a wanton is that he does not care about his will. He does not
care about the sort of person he is or might become.
An unwilling addict? |
(2) The
unwilling addict: Let us now imagine a second addict, someone whose
physiological addiction is identical with that of our imaginary wanton. What
might make this second addict different from the wanton is his second-order
volitions which make him an unhappy and unwilling addict. This second addict
struggles against his addiction, but these desires are too powerful for him to
withstand, and invariably, in the end, they overcome him. He is an unwilling addict, helplessly violated by his own desires. This
is a human person, but one divided against himself. If there is to be any
progress in his life it would seem that this could only be by achieving some
degree of integration between his first and second-order volitions. He has to
be able to make his second-order preferences actual in his life, but finds that
he cannot do so. Frankfurt’s argument is that such a person cannot be described
as having ‘freedom of the will’. It is not that this unwilling addict is not
able to do what he wants, but rather that his will is not free. It is this that
leads him to say puzzling things to the effect that the force that makes him
take drugs is not his own. He does not have the will he wants, whereas the
wanton simply doesn’t care which of his first-order desires is driving him.
Gordon Gekko, the ruthless corporate raider, played as hero |
3 (3) The willing addict: Let us consider a third kind of
addict. Suppose that his addiction (says
Frankfurt) has the same physiological basis and the same irresistible thrust as
the addictions of the unwilling and wanton addicts, but that he is altogether
delighted with his condition. He is a willing addict, who would not have things
any other way. If the grip of his addiction should somehow weaken, he would do
whatever he could to reinstate it; if his desire for the drug should begin to fade,
he would take steps to renew its intensity. Is this willing addict’s will
free? No, it isn’t, for his desire to take the drug will be effective
regardless of whether or not he wants this desire to constitute his will. But
when he tales the drug, he takes it freely and of his own free will. How are we
to regard this person? How is he, for example, different from someone who is
driven by an overwhelming sexual desire of whatever kind? Or from someone whose
life is driven by a desire to see himself as a Master of the Universe? Someone, say, like Gordon Gekko in the
1987 film Wall Street and his many
real life golems?
This is simply a schematic version of a theory that the author himself describes as a rough sketch, but it is enough for immediate purposes. It raises a number of questions that are relevant directly or obliquely to our reading of Kierkegaard. You might like to think, for example, about some of these:
(a) What kind of person is most directly implied by the simple
theory of Utilitarianism? (I’m thinking of Bentham’s original version?)
(b) How might we envisage a person progressing on this scheme?
How might a person get himself to care about the sort of person he is and
actively create new second-order volitions?
(c) Is there any natural line of development for a person
pursuing such a moral career? What his will be like? Would it take him in
specific directions? Would we all end up as the same sort of person?
(d) Does a man (or a woman) have an ultimately stable identity if
their character is that of someone who fits in well, even perfectly, with their
social situation? We might think, for example, of Robert, Earl of Grantham and his wife,
Cora, in the TV series, Downton Abbey. Here are two people who seem to be
tailored for their lives as model aristocrats of a now bygone era. Are their
identities stable or admirable?
(e) How does this link up –if at all – with Kierkegaard’s scheme
of three spheres or stages of life?
No comments:
Post a Comment