Concluding: The Concept of a Person
Harry Frankfurt, best known for 'On Bullshit' and 'Truth' |
IV
«My theory concerning the freedom of the will accounts
easily for our disinclination to allow this freedom to be enjoyed by ay members
of any species inferior to our own. It also satisfies another condition that
must be met by any such theory, by making it apparent why the freedom of the
will should be regarded as desirable.The enjoyment of a free will means the satisfaction of certain desires –
desires of the second or of higher orders – whereas its absence means their
frustration. The satisfactions at stake are those which accrue to a person of
whom it may be said that his will is his own. The corresponding frustrations
are those suffered by a person of whom it may be said that he is estranged from
himself, or that he finds himself hapless or a passive bystander to the forces
that move him.
«A person who is free to do what he wants to do may yet not
be in a position to have the will he wants. Suppose, however, that he enjoys
both freedom of action and freedom of the will. Then he is not only free to do
what he wants to do; he is also free to want what he wants to want. It seems to
me that he has in that case, all the freedom it is possible to desire or to
conceive. There are other good things in life, and he may not possess some of
them. But there is nothing in the way of freedom that he lacks.
«It is far from clear that certain other theories of the
freedom of the will meet these elementary but essential conditions: that it be
understandable why we desire this freedom and why we refuse to ascribe it to
animals. Consider, for example, Roderick Chrisholm’s quaint version of the
doctrine that human freedom entails an absence of causal determination.[i]
Whenever a person performs a free action, according to Chrisholm, it’s a
miracle. The motion of a person’s hand, when the person moves it, is the
outcome of a series of physical causes; but some event in this series, “and
presumably one of those that took place within the brain, was caused by the
agent and not by any other events” (18). A free agent has, therefore, “a
prerogative which some would attribute only to God: each of us, when we act, is
a prime mover unmoved” (23).
«This account fails to provide any basis for doubting that
animals of subhuman species enjoy the freedom it defines. Chrisholm says
nothing that makes it seem less likely that a rabbit performs a miracle when it
moves its leg than that a man does so when he moves his hand. But why, in any
case should anyone care whether he can interrupt the natural order of causes in
the way Chrisholm describes? Chrisholm offers no reason for believing that
there is a discernible difference between the experience of a man who
miraculously initiates a series of causes when he moves his hand and a man who
moves his hand without any such breach of the normal causal sequence. There
appears to be no concrete basis for preferring to be involved in the one state
of affairs rather than in the other.[ii]
«It is generally supposed that, in addition to satisfying
the two conditions I have mentioned, a satisfactory theory of the freedom of
the will necessarily provides an analysis of one of the conditions of moral
responsibility. The most common recent approach to the problem of understanding
the freedom of the will has been, indeed, to enquire what is entailed by the
assumption that someone is morally responsible for what he has done. In my
view, however, the relation between moral responsibility and the freedom of the
will has been very widely misunderstood. It is not true that a person is
morally responsible for what he has done only if his will was free when he did
it. He may be morally responsible for having done it even though his will was
not free at all.
«A person’s will is
free only if he is free to have the will he wants. This means that, with regard
to any of his first-order desires, he is free either to make that desire his
will or to make some other first-order desire his will instead. Whatever his
will, then, the will of the person whose will is free could have been
otherwise; he could have done otherwise than to constitute his will as he did.
It is a vexed question just how “he could have done otherwise” is to be
understood in context such as this one. But although this question is important
to the theory of freedom, it has no bearing on the theory of moral
responsibility. For the assumption that a person is morally responsible for
what he has done does not entail that the person was in a position to have
whatever will he wanted.
«This assumption does
entail that the person did what he did freely, or that he did it of his own
free will. It is a mistake, however, to believe that someone acts freely only
when he is free to do whatever he wants or that he acts of his own free will
only if his will is free. Suppose that a person has done what he wanted to do,
that he did it because he wanted to do it, and that the will be which he was
moved when he did was his will because it was the will he wanted. Then he did
it freely and of his own free will. Even supposing that he could have done
otherwise, he would not have done otherwise; and even supposing that he could
have had a different will, he would not have wanted his will to differ from
what it was. Moreover, since the will that moved when he acted was his will
because he wanted it to be, he cannot claim that his will was forced upon him
or that he was a passive bystander to its constitution. Under these conditions,
it is quite irrelevant to the evaluation of his moral responsibility to inquire
whether the alternatives that he opted against were actually available to him.[iii]
«In illustration, consider a third kind of addict. Suppose
that his addiction has the same physiological basis and the same irresistible
thrust as the addictions of the unwilling and wanton addicts, but that he is
altogether delighted with his condition. He is a willing addict, who would not
have things any other way. If the grip of his addiction should somehow weaken,
he would do whatever he could to reinstate it; if his desire for the drug
should begin to fade, he would take steps to renew its intensity.
«The willing addict’s will is not free, for his desire to
take the drug will be effective regardless of whether or not he wants this
desire to constitute his will. But when he takes the drug, he takes it freely
and of his own free will. I am inclined to understand his situation as
involving the overdetermination of his first-order desire to take the drug.
This desire is his effective desire because he is physiologically addicted. But
it is his effective desire also because he wants it to be. His will is outside
his control, but, by his second-order desire that his desire for the drug
should be effective, he has made his will his own. Given that it is therefore
not only because of his addiction that his desire for the drug is effective, he
may be morally responsible for taking the drug.
«My conception of the freedom of the will appears to be
neutral with regard to the problem of determinism. It seems conceivable that it
should be causally determined that a person is free to want what he wants to
want. If this is conceivable, then it might be causally determined that a person
enjoys a free will. There is no more than an innocuous appearance of paradox in
the proposition that it is determined, ineluctably and by forces beyond their
control, that certain people have free wills and that others do not. There is
no incoherence in the proposition that some agency other than a person’s own is
responsible (even morally
responsible) for the fact that he enjoys or fails to enjoy freedom of the will.
It is possible that a person should be morally responsible for what he does of
his own free will and that some other person should also be morally responsible
for his having done it.[iv]
«On the other hand, it seems conceivable that it should come
about chance by chance that a person is free to have the will he wants. If this
is conceivable, then it might be a matter of chance that certain people enjoy
freedom of the will and that certain others do not. Perhaps it is also
conceivable, as a number of philosophers believe, for states of affairs to come
about in a way other than by chance or as the outcome of a sequence of natural
causes. If indeed it is conceivable for the relevant states of affairs to come
about in some third way, then it is also possible that a person should in that
third way come to enjoy the freedom of the will. »
[i]
“Freedom and Action”, in K. Lehrer (ed.), Freedom
and Determinism (New York: Random House, 1966), pp. 11-44.
[ii] I
am no suggesting that the alleged difference between the two states of affairs
is unverifiable. On the contrary, physiologists might well be able to show that
Chrisholm’s conditions for a free action are not satisfied, by establishing
that there is no relevant brain event for which a sufficient physical cause
cannot be found.
[iii]For
another discussion of the considerations that cast doubt on the principle that
a person is morally responsible for what he has done only if he could have done
otherwise, see my “Alternate Possibilities and Moral Responsibility.”
[iv]
There is a difference between being fully responsible and being solely
responsible. Suppose that the willing addict has been made an addict by the
deliberate and calculated work of another. Then it may be that both the addict
and this other person are fully responsible for the addict’s taking the drug,
while neither of them is solely responsible for it. That there is a distinction
between full moral responsibility and sole moral responsibility is apparent in
the following example. A certain light can be turned on and off by flicking
either of two switches and each of these switches is simultaneously flicked to
the “on” position by a different person, neither of whom is aware of the other.
Either person is solely responsible for the light’s going on, nor do they share
responsibility in the sense that each is partially responsible; rather each is
fully responsible.
No comments:
Post a Comment